Add new comment

Electoral impossibilities


Polling station
One advantage of the UK voting system is that nobody could possibly fail to understand how it works. Everybody has one vote, in every constituency the candidate with most votes wins, and the party that wins the majority of constituencies goes on to form the government. Simple.

However, the disadvantages are well-known. Dividing the electorate up into constituencies means that the party in government doesn't necessarily have the largest share of the vote. The first-past-the-post system turns the election into a two-horse — or at most a three-horse — race, which leaves swathes of the population un-represented, forces tactical voting, and turns election campaigns into mud-slinging contests.

There are many alternative voting systems, but is there a perfect one? The answer, in a mathematical sense, is no. To see why, let's remind ourselves of what an election is actually trying to do. There is a population of voters, each of whom, if pressed hard enough, can come up with a preference ranking of the candidates: whom they like most, whom they like least, and everything in between, with some candidates possibly occupying equal position. Ideally, a voting system should take these millions of preference rankings as input, and return a single ranking of candidates that makes reasonable democratic sense. The government can then be formed on the basis of this single ranking.

Will you vote for him? Image: World Economic Forum

But what's democratic sense? First of all, we clearly don't want there to be a dictator, so the system should reflect the wishes of more than just one individual. Secondly, the system should reflect voters' wishes reasonably accurately. At the very least we should require that if all voters prefer candidate x to candidate y, then x should come above y in the final result (this condition is sometimes called unanimity). Also, there shouldn't be room for ambiguity: the voting system should always return exactly one clear final ranking (this condition is known as universality).

In the 1950s the economist Kenneth Arrow asked himself whether there can be a voting system which satisfies these pretty minimal criteria. He added one slightly more subtle condition: in the final result, whether one candidate is ranked above another, say Gordon Brown above David Cameron, should only depend on how individual voters ranked Brown compared to Cameron. It shouldn't depend on how they ranked either of the two compared to a third candidate, for example Nick Clegg.

For example, suppose that Brown has just won the election, having come top of the final ranking, when Clegg becomes embroiled in a scandal, which sees him slide to the bottom of all voters' preference rankings. Then this should not have any effect on the fact that Brown was more popular than Cameron: a re-run of the election should still return Brown as the winner, as long as voters didn't change their relative rankings of Brown and Cameron. Arrow called this condition independence of irrelevant alternatives. In our example, poor Clegg has become irrelevant, but this shouldn't effect the contest between Brown and Cameron. Independence of irrelevant alternatives is an important condition because non-compliance of a voting system means that the ranking of outside candidates can have an effect on the outcome.

Gordon Brown

Or do you prefer him? Image: Pazok.

Arrow proved mathematically that if there are three or more candidates and two or more voters, no voting system that works by taking voters' preference rankings as input and returns a single ranking as output can satisfy all the four conditions. Put differently, only a dictatorship (in which one voter's ranking determines the result) can simultaneously satisfy unanimity, universality and independence of irrelevant alternatives. His theorem, called Arrow's Impossibility Theorem helped to earn him the 1972 Nobel Prize in Economics.

As an example of how Arrow's theorem plays out in practice, think of the first-past-the-post system. The winner will be the candidate with most top votes, the runner-up the candidate with second-most top choices, and so on, with all the lower rankings being ignored. This system satisfies the first three conditions, but it can fail independence of irrelevant alternatives.

To see why, suppose that in a direct election with four candidates (Brown, Cameron, Clegg, and Xwoman) voters' preferences split into four groups:

 Group 1: 41%Group 2: 39%Group 3: 17%Group 4: 3%
1st preferenceBrownCameronCleggXwoman
2nd preferenceCleggCleggBrownCameron
3rd preferenceCameronBrownCameronClegg
4th preferenceXwomanXwomanXwomanBrown

 

Then Brown (41%) wins over Cameron (39%), with Clegg coming third (17%), and Xwoman last (3%). Now suppose Xwoman does something terrible and slides to the bottom of all voters' rankings. We get the groups:

 Group 1: 41%Group 2: 39%Group 3: 17%Group 4: 3%
1st preferenceBrownCameronCleggCameron
2nd preferenceCleggCleggBrownClegg
3rd preferenceCameronBrownCameronBrown
4th preferenceXwomanXwomanXwomanXwoman

 

Then Cameron (42%) wins over Brown (41%) with Clegg coming third (17%), and Xwoman last (0%). So even though no voter has changed his or her relative preference of Brown versus Cameron (58% still prefer Brown to Cameron) Cameron has beaten Brown to the top spot.

An alternative to first-past-the-post which does satisfy independence of irrelevant alternative is to have candidates battle it out in pair-wise contests. In a three candidate election with Brown, Cameron and Clegg, you first pit Brown against Cameron: if there are more voters preferring Brown to Cameron than Cameron to Brown, then Brown is ranked first, and vice versa. Then you pit Cameron against Clegg to find the relative ranking of these two, and finally you pit Clegg against Brown. This is arguably more democratic than first-past-the-post, as any winner would be preferred to the other candidates by a majority of the electorate.

But as Arrow's theorem predicts, this system has another potential flaw. Suppose that voters split into three groups with the following rankings:

Group 1: 34%Group 2: 33%Group 3: 33%
BrownCameronClegg
CameronCleggBrown
CleggBrownCameron

 

Then the Brown-Cameron battle is won by Brown (67% of the electorate prefer him to Cameron) and the Cameron-Clegg battle is won by Cameron (67% prefer him to Clegg), so the ranking should be [Brown, Cameron, Clegg]. However, the Brown-Clegg battle is won by Clegg (66% prefer him to Brown), so Clegg should really come above Brown. What we have here is called a Condorcet cycle: Brown beats Cameron, Cameron beats Clegg, but Clegg beats Brown. There is no way of coming up with a definite ranking, and a majority of the electorate will be unhappy no matter who is chosen as winner, because they preferred someone else. This system violates our third condition of universality.

Nick Clegg

Or maybe him? Image: David Spender.

So does Arrow's theorem mean that democracy is impossible? Not unless you're a mathematical absolutist. The theorem doesn't say that every voting system always returns horribly unfair results, but that there always is a theoretical possibility that one of the four conditions might be breached if voters happen to vote in a particular way. Whether or not these breaches are a terrible thing depends on how often they are likely to happen — you might argue that the cyclical split in the last example is unlikely to occur in a general election — and how important you think the condition is that's being violated. Non-dictatorship is clearly pretty fundamental, but some people argue that we could do without independence of irrelevant alternatives. Other people support voting systems in which candidates aren't ranked, but rated, as happens for example in approval voting (see Plus article Approving a president), in which people are simply asked to approve or not approve of a candidate, and which escapes Arrow's theorem. It's a question of carefully weighing up pros and cons to choose the best system. And while the first-past-the-post system is undoubtedly crude, there is also an argument for simplicity: the fairest system is of no use if it's so complicated that voters end up not bothering to vote.

Arrow's theorem gives mathematical backing to something we already know from experience: that it's really hard to design a system that produces a reasonably fair result in all circumstances. But when it comes to democracy mathematics is as limited as it is essential. It can do nothing about the social and political issues that keep people from exercising, or being able to exercise, their right to vote.

Filtered HTML

  • Web page addresses and email addresses turn into links automatically.
  • Allowed HTML tags: <a href hreflang> <em> <strong> <cite> <code> <ul type> <ol start type> <li> <dl> <dt> <dd>
  • Lines and paragraphs break automatically.