icon

Playing billiards on doughnuts

Marianne Freiberger Share this page

Thanks to Corinna Ulcigrai of the University of Bristol for her help with this article.

Mathematicians love a game of billiards. Not because they like being in the pub (though many do), but because billiards is a great example of a chaotic dynamical system (see Chaos on the billiard table). In mathematical billiard the ball is assumed to have no mass, so it experiences no friction. Once you put it in motion, it will keep going, tracing out a trajectory on the table. We ignore those trajectories that hit one of the pockets, so we can assume that the ball is never swallowed up — it will keep going forever.

Reflection

As you'll know from real billiards, it's hard to predict the trajectory of a ball beyond its first few bounces off the sides of the table. If you get the initial direction just right, it might fall into a regular pattern, such as bouncing back and forth between two opposite points on the table (see the figure on the right). But usually, the ball sets off on a long, complicated and jagged journey. How can you know which initial direction gives you which behaviour? And if the ball doesn't fall into a regular pattern, will it eventually visit every part of the table? Questions like these seem hard to answer, but mathematicians have developed a beautiful trick: turn the table into a surface on which the ball travels along straight lines without ever bouncing off anything. Then use the beautiful mathematics of surfaces to understand the trajectories. To see how it works, start by....

Reflecting the table, not the ball

Let’s start with a table that has the simplest possible shape, a square. Label its corners $A,$ $B,$ $C$ and $D$. Now imagine the ball starts somewhere near the bottom edge and heads off in a north-easterly direction, eventually hitting the right-hand edge of the square, its trajectory forming an angle $\alpha $ with the edge.

Reflection

Now here’s the trick: reflect the table in the edge the ball bounces off of and continue the trajectory of the ball in the reflected copy of the table. This continuation gives you a straight line. So rather than drawing the jagged trajectory of the ball inside a single square, simply reflect the square in a side whenever the ball hits that side, and represent the trajectory as a straight line continuing in the reflected square.

Reflection

Do the same again when the ball hits the next wall. After reflecting the square a few times as you follow the ball (twice in our example) you will notice that the new copy of the square has its corners labelled in exactly the same clockwise order as the original one. When that happens, forget about that new copy and instead continue the trajectory on the original square that had its corners labelled in the same way, in the direction indicated by the angle $\alpha .$

Reflection

The right most square has its corners labelled in exactly the same way as the original, left-most square. So we can indicated the ball's trajectory in the original square and forget about the right-most one.

By inspecting what happens to a square when you repeatedly reflect it in its sides, you will see that you only need four copies of the square table to capture the trajectory of a ball — all other copies you produce will have their corners labelled in the same way as one of these four. So rather than continuing the trajectory on a new copy, you move onto one of the four squares you already have.

Reflection

The four squares together form a bigger square, which we call $S.$ When a trajectory leaves $S$ at its right edge, it reappears at the exact opposite point on the left edge. If it leaves $S$ at its left, it reappears at the exact opposite point on the right. Similarly when a trajectory leaves $S$ at its top edge, it reappears at the exact opposite point on the bottom edge, and if it leaves at the bottom it reappears at the top. So you might as well glue the top edge to the bottom edge and the right edge to the left one, with opposite points being glued together. When you do this you get a doughnut shape, technically known as a torus. The trajectory on the square $S$ turns into a continuous line on the torus.

Reflection

A torus with a trajectory marked. Image: Andrea Gambassi and Corinna Ulcigrai.

Round and round

The way we have set things up means that any trajectory on the square table, no matter how complicated, turns into a collection of parallel lines on the square $S,$ whose ends join up when you glue the edges to form the torus. Curves on the torus that arise in this way have a special name. They are called geodesics — and mathematicians know a lot about them. (Technically, they are called flat geodesics as they are define by the "flat" metric the torus inherits from the square $S.$)

One thing they know, which is easy to see, is that some geodesics are closed loops: they might wind around the torus a number of times but then return to where they started. An example is a geodesic that comes from a vertical or a horizontal line on $S.$ On the torus such a geodesic winds once around or through the hole.

Reflection

Another example is shown in the figure below. It’s easy to see that once you have glued the edges of $S$, the ends join up so you get another closed geodesic.

Reflection

What kind of trajectories do these closed geodesics correspond to on the original billiard table? To see this, simply reflect each square back to the original copy (which has corners labelled $A$, $B$, $C$, $D$ in clockwise order) and see where any piece of trajectory it contains goes. This shows that a geodesic that comes from a vertical or horizontal line corresponds to a periodic trajectory: the ball forever bounces back and forth between two opposite points on the edge of table (left in the image below). Similarly our third example, where the geodesic corresponds to two line segments on $S$, corresponds to another periodic trajectory: here the ball travels round and round between the mid points of the four edges of the table (right in the image below). This is true generally: a closed geodesic, since it ends where it started, corresponds to a periodic trajectory, and vice versa.

Reflection

Luckily, mathematicians know exactly how to characterise those closed geodesics on the torus. Any geodesic corresponds to a collection of parallel line segments on the square $S$, that is, line segments that have the same slope. In our example above, the horizontal line has a slope of 0, the vertical line has infinite slope, and the third example comes with a slope of 1. More generally, mathematicians have proved that a geodesic is closed exactly when the corresponding slope of lines on the square $S$ is a rational number: one that can be written as $p/q$ where $p$ and $q$ are whole numbers.

If the slope of the lines on $S$ is an irrational number — one that can’t be expressed as a fraction, such as $\sqrt{2}$ — then the geodesic never returns to where it started. What is more, as it winds round and round the torus forever, it eventually fills up all of it, getting arbitrarily close to every point on it. This result translates back to trajectories on the original billiard table. If a trajectory is not periodic (corresponding to a closed geodesic), then it eventually fills up the table, getting arbitrarily close to every point on it. What is more, you can also show that the trajectory visits each part of the table in equal measure: if you take two regions of the table whose areas are equal, then the trajectory will spend an equal amount of time in both. That’s quite an amazing dichotomy. Either a trajectory is periodic, it retraces the same path again and again, or it fills up the whole table in equal measure. There is nothing in between. (This is known as the Veech dichotomy after the mathematician W.A. Veech.)

The correspondence between periodic trajectories and rational numbers also tells us how likely we are to produce a periodic trajectory by shooting the ball in a random direction. Although there are infinitely many rational numbers and infinitely many irrational ones, the infinity of irrational numbers is "bigger" than the infinity of rational numbers (see Counting numbers). So much so that if you pick a number at random, your chance of picking a rational one is zero. Therefore, if you shoot a ball in a random direction, your chance of producing a periodic trajectory is zero too.

Different table, more holes

A square table is not the only one you can turn into a surface. The trick works whenever your table is a polygon (a shape whose sides are straight lines) whose corner angles are of the form $p/q \times \pi $ where $p$ and $q$ are whole numbers. Billiards played on a table with this shape is called rational polygonal billiards. For example, if your table is a triangle with corner angles $\pi /8,$ $\pi /2$ and $3\pi /8,$ then the reflection process will give you an octagon made up of 16 copies of the triangle, all meeting at the $\pi /8$ corner. When you glue opposite sides, you get a torus with two holes in it (see here to find out why). Whatever polygon you start with, as long as the angles have the correct form, you end up with a torus with some number of holes.

Reflection

Image courtesy Corinna Ulcigrai.

Proving results about trajectories on these more complicated surfaces can be harder than for the simple torus, but luckily a whole box of mathematical tools has been developed to understand such surfaces. For example, a given surface can be deformed by shrinking and stretching. One thing you can do is deform a surface so that a long and complicated piece of geodesic is shrunk down to a manageable size. There are ways of doing this while at the same time keeping track of what happens to other features of the surface and its geodesics. What used to be a long and jagged piece of trajectory on the billiard table has now turned into a nice and short piece of geodesic on the surface.

Barrier

The dichotomy does not necessarily hold on a rectangular table with a barrier.

Using this beautiful trick you can then prove results about those long and jagged trajectories on the original table. For example, one natural question to ask is for what kind of table the dichotomy above holds: that a trajectory is either periodic or fills up the whole table in equal measure. Mathematicians have been able to prove that it holds when the table is a regular polygon and whenever the reflecting process gives rise to a regular polygon (a polygon whose sides all have the same lengths and whose internal angles are all equal), with the corresponding surface coming from gluing together opposite parallel edges. But there are also tables for which this isn't the case and the dichotomy doesn't hold. H. Masur and J. Smillie, relying on previous work by Veech, realised that this is the case on a rectangular table that has a barrier in it, as shown in the image. In this case trajectories that are not periodic do fill up the whole table, but they may spend more time in one part of the table than another. But the general question of which rational polygonal billiards satisfy the dichotomy and which don't is still wide open!


About this article

Corinna Ulcigrai

This article is based on an interview with Corinna Ulcigrai, a Reader in Pure Mathematics at the University of Bristol. Corinna was born in Trieste, Italy, in 1980. She obtained her diploma in Mathematics from the Scuola Normale Superiore in Pisa (2002) and defended her PhD in mathematics at Princeton University (2007), under the supervision of Ya. G. Sinai (Abel Prize Winner 2014). Her research is in the area of dynamical systems and ergodic theory. She is one of the few international experts in Teichmüller dynamics in the UK and has studied dynamical and chaotic properties of polygonal billiards and flows on surfaces. Corinna was awarded the European Mathematical Society prize for young mathematicians at the 2012 European Congress of Mathematics and was a recipient of the 2013 Whitehead Prize of the London Mathematical Society. She is married to a mathematician and has a young child.

Marianne Freiberger, Editor of Plus, interviewed Corinna at the British Mathematical Colloquium in London in April 2014.

Comments

Permalink

How would things work out if we conceive of a 3-D billiards, theoretically speaking? I imagine it would be equivalent to a 4-D torus. Does the dichotomy extend to higher dimensions too?